StartseiteGruppenForumMehrZeitgeist
Web-Site durchsuchen
Diese Seite verwendet Cookies für unsere Dienste, zur Verbesserung unserer Leistungen, für Analytik und (falls Sie nicht eingeloggt sind) für Werbung. Indem Sie LibraryThing nutzen, erklären Sie dass Sie unsere Nutzungsbedingungen und Datenschutzrichtlinie gelesen und verstanden haben. Die Nutzung unserer Webseite und Dienste unterliegt diesen Richtlinien und Geschäftsbedingungen.

Ergebnisse von Google Books

Auf ein Miniaturbild klicken, um zu Google Books zu gelangen.

Lädt ...

Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue (Routledge Nietzsche Studies)

von Lester H. Hunt

MitgliederRezensionenBeliebtheitDurchschnittliche BewertungDiskussionen
371665,546 (3)1
In Ecce Homo (1908) Friedrich Nietzsche calls himself "the first immoralist" and adds "that makes me the annihilator par excellence". Lester Hunt examines this and other radical claims in order to show that Nietzsche does have a coherent ethical and political philosophy. He uses Nietzsche's writings as a starting point for a critique of a wider, contemporary ethical project - one that should inform our lives as well as our thoughts.… (mehr)
Keine
Lädt ...

Melde dich bei LibraryThing an um herauszufinden, ob du dieses Buch mögen würdest.

Keine aktuelle Diskussion zu diesem Buch.

» Siehe auch 1 Erwähnung

Although he doesn't quite admit it, Lester H. Hunt's work in this volume consists of a set of "good-faith straw men," if we can allow for the possibility of such a thing. Throughout the book he abstracts Nietzsche's "arguments" from disparate assertions and injunctions, but works to give Nietzsche the benefit of the doubt in terms of what must be inferred. In many cases, the results are perceptive and interesting, and the subtopics of Nietzsche's vitalism, anti-statism, experimentalism, perspectivism, etc. are framed usefully. I agree with Hunt that Nietzsche's anti-morality is an opposition to establishment moralism (capital-M Morality, in Hunt's usage) rather than to the existence of moralities, which are necessarily diverse under the conditions of Nietzschean perspectivism. I especially liked the well-founded observation that "Nietzsche's ethical relativism amounts to ... a moral polytheism" (134).

The Achilles's heel of Hunt's method in this book is exposed on page 100, where he writes of Nietzsche, "[F]or the sake of the cogency of his system he must at any rate be able to answer the argument ..." (emphasis added). But this passage, so typical of Hunt and his approach to Nietzsche, plainly ignores the aphorism from "Arrows and Maxims" (in Twilight of the Idols): "I distrust all systematizers and avoid them. The will to a system is a lack of integrity." Nietzsche was not building a system in either of what Hunt calls his "immoralist" and "legislating" modes (150). The existence of conflicts among Nietzsche's ideas is a testament to their vitality. They derive from something other than the "will to a system," which would reduce his work to a uniform medium from which stresses had been removed.

A key shortcoming among Hunt's interpretations here is his tendency to pigeonhole the scope of any given idea (or posited "argument") of Nietzsche's as either individual-psychological or social-ethical, and in Hunt's conclusions he focuses on the tension between the contents of the two categories. Nietzsche himself, however, insisted that "our body is but a social structure composed of many souls ... What happens here is what happens in every well-constructed and happy commonwealth, namely, that the governing class identifies itself with the successes of the commonwealth" (Beyond Good & Evil §19), showing that this distinction imposed by Hunt is alien to Nietzsche's approach to the questions involved. Just as Nietzsche discountenanced the received dichotomy of mind and body in the philosophical tradition, so too he rejected the "social" and "individual" as rigid categories, preferring to apply the evident mechanisms of one to the opaque operations of the other. So the tension that Hunt tries to demonstrate at a "systemic," categorical level really resides at an atomic scale within the difficulty of Nietzsche's thought.

I am sympathetic to much of what Hunt writes in this book, but with my misgivings about his method, I can hardly accept his conclusions. As always, I appreciate another voice encouraging me to grapple with Nietzsche's texts.
3 abstimmen paradoxosalpha | Jan 15, 2018 |
keine Rezensionen | Rezension hinzufügen
Du musst dich einloggen, um "Wissenswertes" zu bearbeiten.
Weitere Hilfe gibt es auf der "Wissenswertes"-Hilfe-Seite.
Gebräuchlichster Titel
Originaltitel
Alternative Titel
Ursprüngliches Erscheinungsdatum
Figuren/Charaktere
Wichtige Schauplätze
Wichtige Ereignisse
Zugehörige Filme
Epigraph (Motto/Zitat)
Widmung
Erste Worte
Zitate
Letzte Worte
Hinweis zur Identitätsklärung
Verlagslektoren
Werbezitate von
Originalsprache
Anerkannter DDC/MDS
Anerkannter LCC

Literaturhinweise zu diesem Werk aus externen Quellen.

Wikipedia auf Englisch (1)

In Ecce Homo (1908) Friedrich Nietzsche calls himself "the first immoralist" and adds "that makes me the annihilator par excellence". Lester Hunt examines this and other radical claims in order to show that Nietzsche does have a coherent ethical and political philosophy. He uses Nietzsche's writings as a starting point for a critique of a wider, contemporary ethical project - one that should inform our lives as well as our thoughts.

Keine Bibliotheksbeschreibungen gefunden.

Buchbeschreibung
Zusammenfassung in Haiku-Form

Aktuelle Diskussionen

Keine

Beliebte Umschlagbilder

Gespeicherte Links

Bewertung

Durchschnitt: (3)
0.5
1
1.5
2
2.5
3 1
3.5
4
4.5
5

Bist das du?

Werde ein LibraryThing-Autor.

 

Über uns | Kontakt/Impressum | LibraryThing.com | Datenschutz/Nutzungsbedingungen | Hilfe/FAQs | Blog | LT-Shop | APIs | TinyCat | Nachlassbibliotheken | Vorab-Rezensenten | Wissenswertes | 204,874,950 Bücher! | Menüleiste: Immer sichtbar